Docsity
Docsity

Prepare for your exams
Prepare for your exams

Study with the several resources on Docsity


Earn points to download
Earn points to download

Earn points by helping other students or get them with a premium plan


Guidelines and tips
Guidelines and tips

Understanding Categorical Syllogisms: Form, Mood, Figure, and Validity, Study notes of Philosophy

The concept of categorical syllogisms, which are arguments consisting of three categorical propositions and containing three distinct terms. It covers the definitions of major term, minor term, and middle term, as well as the standard premise order. Additionally, it discusses the concepts of mood and figure in categorical syllogisms and provides examples of valid and invalid arguments.

What you will learn

  • What is the difference between the major term and the minor term in a categorical syllogism?
  • How do you determine the mood and figure of a categorical syllogism?
  • What are the three distinct terms in a categorical syllogism?

Typology: Study notes

2021/2022

Uploaded on 08/05/2022

hal_s95
hal_s95 🇵🇭

4.4

(652)

10K documents

1 / 6

Toggle sidebar

This page cannot be seen from the preview

Don't miss anything!

bg1
1
5.1 Categorical Syllogisms
We have learned a great deal about categorical propositions. In this lesson, we will learn
how to construct valid arguments out of categorical propositions.
1. Standard Argument Form: First, recall that an argument is a set of premises which
support some conclusion. In this section, we will be specifically concerned with the kind
of argument called a “syllogism.”
Syllogism: An argument consisting of three statements: TWO premises and ONE
conclusion.
Furthermore, we’ll specifically be concerned with what is known as a “categorical
syllogism.”
Categorical syllogism: A syllogism consisting of three categorical propositions,
and containing THREE DISTINCT TERMS, each of which appears in exactly two of
the three propositions.
So, what are these 3 terms mentioned? Consider the following syllogism:
1. All mammals are creatures that have hair.
2. All dogs are mammals.
3. Therefore, all dogs are creatures that have hair.
See the three colors (red, blue, and green)? There are THREE different terms in this
argument (besides the quantifiers and the copulas). The three different terms are called
the “major term”, the “minor term”, and the “middle term.” Notice that the conclusion
only contains TWO of the three terms (red and blue), but one of the terms (green) is
found only in the premises. Here are some definitions:
Major Term: The predicate term of the conclusion
(above, the blue term, creatures that have hair”)
Minor Term: The subject term of the conclusion
(above, the red term, “dogs”)
Middle Term: The term that does NOT appear in the conclusion
(above, the green term, “mammals”)
Standard premise order: Finally, note that premise 1 contains the major term, while
premise 2 contains the minor term. Premise 1 is therefore called the major premise,
while premise 2 is called the minor premise. The standard form demands that the
major premise (i.e., the one containing the major term) ALWAYS be listed first.
pf3
pf4
pf5

Partial preview of the text

Download Understanding Categorical Syllogisms: Form, Mood, Figure, and Validity and more Study notes Philosophy in PDF only on Docsity!

5.1 Categorical Syllogisms

We have learned a great deal about categorical propositions. In this lesson, we will learn how to construct valid arguments out of categorical propositions.

1. Standard Argument Form: First, recall that an argument is a set of premises which support some conclusion. In this section, we will be specifically concerned with the kind of argument called a “syllogism.”

Syllogism: An argument consisting of three statements: TWO premises and ONE conclusion.

Furthermore, we’ll specifically be concerned with what is known as a “categorical syllogism.”

Categorical syllogism: A syllogism consisting of three categorical propositions, and containing THREE DISTINCT TERMS, each of which appears in exactly two of the three propositions.

So, what are these 3 terms mentioned? Consider the following syllogism:

  1. All mammals are creatures that have hair.
  2. All dogs are mammals.
  3. Therefore, all dogs are creatures that have hair.

See the three colors (red, blue, and green)? There are THREE different terms in this argument (besides the quantifiers and the copulas). The three different terms are called the “ major term ”, the “ minor term ”, and the “ middle term .” Notice that the conclusion only contains TWO of the three terms (red and blue), but one of the terms (green) is found only in the premises. Here are some definitions:

Major Term: The predicate term of the conclusion (above, the blue term, “creatures that have hair ”) Minor Term: The subject term of the conclusion (above, the red term, “ dogs ”) Middle Term: The term that does NOT appear in the conclusion (above, the green term, “ mammals ”)

Standard premise order: Finally, note that premise 1 contains the major term, while premise 2 contains the minor term. Premise 1 is therefore called the major premise , while premise 2 is called the minor premise. The standard form demands that the major premise (i.e., the one containing the major term) ALWAYS be listed first.

2. Mood and Figure: Now that we know the correct FORM of categorical syllogisms, we can learn some tools that will help us to determine when such syllogisms are valid or invalid. All categorical syllogisms have what is called a “ mood ” and a “ figure .”

Mood: The mood of a categorical syllogism is a series of three letters corresponding to the type of proposition the major premise, the minor premise, and the conclusion are (A, E, I, or O).

When determining the mood of a categorical syllogism, you need to figure out which of the four forms of categorical proposition each line of the argument is (A, E, I, or O). For instance, in the argument above about dogs, ALL THREE statements are “A” propositions (of the form “All S are P”), so the mood of that argument would be “AAA”. Here is a syllogism that has a little more diversity:

  1. No states with coastlines are states that are landlocked.
  2. Some U.S. states are states that are landlocked.
  3. Therefore, some U.S. states are not states with coastlines.

Let’s figure out the FORM of the premises and the conclusion:

  1. No S are P (E)
  2. Some S are P (I)
  3. Some S are not P (O)

So, the mood of this proposition is “EIO”. Just to review, note also that the major term is states with coastlines , the minor term is U.S. states , and the middle term is states that are landlocked. Now, let’s learn about “ figure .”

Figure: The figure of a categorical syllogism is a number which corresponds to the placement of the two middle terms.

For instance, consider the argument from earlier:

  1. All mammals are creatures that have hair.
  2. All dogs are mammals.
  3. Therefore, all dogs are creatures that have hair.

Notice that the middle term in the major premise is on the LEFT, while the middle term in the minor premise is on the RIGHT. Whenever this happens, we say that the argument has “figure 1.” Altogether, there are four possible figures:

3. Valid Argument Forms: Now that we know about the proper FORMS of categorical syllogisms, and also how to assess what MOOD and FIGURE each argument has, we can use some charts to assess when an argument is valid or invalid.

Unconditionally Valid Forms: There are 15 combinations of mood and figure that are valid from the Boolean standpoint (we call these “ unconditionally valid ” argument forms). This chart depicts ALL of 15 the unconditionally valid argument forms

Recall this argument from earlier:

  1. All mammals are creatures that have hair.
  2. All dogs are mammals.
  3. Therefore, all dogs are creatures that have hair.

Its mood was “ AAA ” since all three propositions are “A” propositions (i.e., they are all of the form “All S are P”). Its figure was “ figure 1 ” since the middle term appears on the left and then on the right (picture the leftmost diagonal line of the “collar flap” diagram). Now we can look up “figure 1 – AAA” in the chart above. If it DOES APPEAR on the chart, then the argument is valid from the Boolean standpoint. If it DOES NOT APPEAR on the chart, then it is invalid from the Boolean standpoint. Since “ figure 1 – AAA ” DOES appear on the chart, the argument is valid !! Let’s try the other one:

  1. No states with coastlines are states that are landlocked.
  2. Some U.S. states are states that are landlocked.
  3. Therefore, some U.S. states are not states with coastlines.

This argument’s mood is “ EIO ”. Its figure is “ figure 2 ”. Let’s look that up on the chart. Sure enough, under “ figure 2 - EIO ” appears on the list!! This argument is valid.

Conditionally Valid Forms: Now, recall that there were some inferences that were NOT valid from the Boolean standpoint which WERE valid from the Aristotelian standpoint— but only IF they were about existing things. The chart above listed argument forms that were valid from BOTH the Boolean AND the Aristotelian standpoint. The chart below lists argument forms that are ONLY valid: (1) from the Aristotelian standpoint, where universal propositions have existential import, and only IF (2) the term listed in the right- hand column actually exists. We call these “ conditionally valid ” argument forms. There are 9 conditionally valid argument forms for categorical syllogisms in addition to the 15 unconditionally valid argument forms:

Recall that the existential fallacy occurred when going from a universal premise to a particular conclusion. Similarly, all of the above “conditionally valid” argument forms have universal premises (“A” or “E”) and a particular conclusion (“I” or “O”). Consider the following argument:

  1. All mammals are creatures that have hair.
  2. All dogs are mammals.
  3. Therefore, some dogs are creatures that have hair.

This argument is an “ AAI ” argument with “ figure 1 ”. This argument does NOT appear on the “unconditionally valid” (Boolean) chart, because it goes from universal premises (which do NOT have existential import) to a particular conclusion (which DOES have existential import), and this sort of inference commits the existential fallacy according to Boole.

But, notice that this form (“ figure 1 – AAI ”) DOES appear on the “conditionally valid” (Aristotelian) chart. So, it IS conditionally valid on the Aristotelian interpretation.